Wednesday, 6 September 2017

The "three hypostases": their Gnostic, Hermetic, Platonic origin


One of the most curious paradoxes of Arianism is that it took to the extreme the doctrine of the "three hypostases", which was of Origen (albeit in a subordinationist sense). The champions of Nicea, including, first and foremost Athanasius, firmly held to one hypostasis of God.

So, to "cure" the Arian heresy, the "orthodox" ultimately resorted to a cure that contained an even more remote heresy, Gnosticism, the infamous "one ousia in three hypostases" invented by the Cappadocian scoundrels.

Don't you believe it?

Read this:

7. Now all these [Gnostics] derived the starting points of their impiety from the philosophers Hermes [Trismegistus], Plato and Aristotle.

8. Now with the heresy of the Ariomaniacs, which has corrupted the Church of God, it is necessary to clarify the matter in their case as well, that you may be able to know that by deceitful sophistry they have filched the dogmas of the ancients.

9. These then teach three hypostases, just as Valentinus the [Gnostic] heresiarch first invented in the book entitled by him 'On the Three Natures'. For he was the first to invent three hypostases and three persons of Father, Son and Holy Spirit, and he is discovered to have filched this from Hermes and Plato.

10. That is also why they again devise a second god created by the Father before the ages, as their esteemed Asterius said, instructed by Hermes surnamed Trismegistus (for this is how he speaks to Asclepius the physician: 'Hear then, Asclepius. The lord and maker of everything, whom we are accustomed to name God, created the second god visible and perceptible as well'). This is also where he acquired his 'only begotten god' instead of from the divine John saying 'only begotten Son' (John 1:18; 3:16, 18).

(Logan AHB, Marcellus of Ancyra (Pseudo-Anthimus), 'On the Holy Church': Text, Translation and Commentary,  © Journal of Theological Studies, NS, Volume 51, Pt. 1, April 2000, p.95 - bolding and italics by MdS - see also @ e-homoreligiosus.blogspot.it, where the full quotation is provided - also in the original Greek - and, although Marcellus of Ancyra is apparently presented in a negative light, it is confirmed that he - not Anthimus of Nicomedia - is the author of On the Holy Church)

So, what is Marcellus of Ancyra saying? That the very core of the Trinitarian Dogma is a Gnostic pollution of Christianity, and that, in turn, the Gnostic Valentinus has filched it from Hermetism.

A banned comment on Tuggy's post in reply to Kimel's

Three Scoundrels: Basil of Caesarea, Gregory of Nazianzus, Gregory of Nyssa

Herebelow is a comment that I had tried to append on Dale Tuggy's post Kimel’s review of What is the Trinity – Part 1 (August 7, 2017 @ trinities.org/blog, in reply to Fr Aidan (Alvin) Kimel's post The Curious Trinity of Dale Tuggy posted on

After several comments there, I found myself banned (probably because I "disturbed the driver" - the same happened to me at Kimel's Blog Eclectic Orthodoxy, BTW). As I believe my comment had some merit, I re-propose it here.

@ John Thiomas [August 10, 2017]
They [Orthodox priests or bishops] accept it [Trinity] because church accepted it and believe that church was led by Holy Spirit in doing so.
[Banned comment, 24 August 2017] To use the expression "[the] church accepted it" implies that someone had to propose it to the Church, first. There is no doubt that in its fully fledged form, it was the Cappadocian scoundrels that proposed it. Either we expose the Trinity starting from this end result (this seems to be the favourite approach, here [at Dale Tuggy's Blog]), OR (which I believe makes more sense) we start from the beginning, from the "original sin" that brought the Church to that end result, that is from the "another God and Lord" (Gr. theos kai kurios eteros) first introduced by Justin Martyr (Dialogue with Trypho, ch. 56 [@ ccel.org]), which screwed up Biblical Strict Monotheism.

Whoever is interested in exposing the fully fledged "trinity", starting from the "original sin", is welcome to comment on this post/comment.

Then whence cometh evil?


The Chaos: Engraving according to Ovid’s description in The Metamorphoses,
in: Michel de Marolles, Paintings of the Temple of the Muses, Paris, Antoine de Sommaville 1655

This post is the ideal continuation of my post Catastrophic Stairway to Freedom (30.01.16, originally posted April 5, 2010). In that post you will also find a hint of what I am getting at here.

Traditionally, Christians have been taught that human evil originated with the "original sin". Traditionally, especially with and after Augustine, the consequence of "original sin" has been interpreted as a true and proper corruption of human nature. While the Catholic Church has always been rather cautious with this extreme conclusion, Protestants have traditionally adopted this notion of human sin as a consequence of the corruption of human nature, in turn as a consequence of "original sin". I will confront this issue in a future post.

But what about cosmic evil (earthquakes, eruptions, floods, tsunamis, diseases, attacks by wild animals, etc.)? Surely it would be grotesque to see also cosmic evil as a consequence of "original sin". Yet there is a strong tradition in this sense, especially in Calvinism.

If anyone wants to know more, including high level literary implications, I recommend reading Calvinism and Cosmic Evil in "Moby-Dick" (T. Walter Herbert, Jr. PMLA, Vol. 84, No. 6 (Oct., 1969), pp. 1613-1619). Just a brief quotation from the paper: 
Melville's presentation of Captain Ahab is heavily influenced by Calvin's interpretation of the Old Testament King Ahab [1 Kings 16-22]. Furthermore, Melville was familiar with a traditional form of attack on Calvinism in which Calvin was accused of having envisaged a God who is a brutal monster. While writing Moby-Dick Melville had at hand a celebrated anti-Calvinist treatise which raises this issue, John Taylor's Scripture Doctrine of Original Sin. [1740; with "A Supplement to the Scripture-doctrine of original sin", 1741]
Unlike the prophet Jonah, also afflicted by a whale, according to God's will, Captain Ahab, by contrast, does not dissolve in a Jonah's terror: although he interprets the whale's attack as an indication of the divine will, he takes it as a cosmic affront and determines to be revenged. Calvin does not try to defend "God's honour", by claiming that the cosmic evil by which humans are afflicted is not willed by God. No, for Calvin cosmic evil is a perfect means by which God afflicts humans: only those who (like Jonah, like King David, like Job - the latter not immediately, but eventually) bow down to God's inscrutable will show that they are the elect. Those whom he has already predestined to be the reprobate (like King Saul, like King Ahab) vainly try to resist God's will. The more they try to act according to what they consider reason, the more they get entangled in God's punishment, wrath and condemnation. 

If there is any doubt about Calvin's position, here are the accusations against which he had to defend  himself, in his own words:
[If God created men with the intention to damn the greater part of them, then the creation was] not an act of love, but of hatred. (...) No beast is so cruel (to say nothing of man) that it would desire to create its young to misery.” (Calvin's Calvinism, trans. Henry Cole (Grand Rapids, Mich., 1950), pp. 213. This volume contains Calvin's two polemical treatises, "The Eternal Predestination of God" and "The Secret Providence of God", with a series of Articles, from which the quotations are taken)
In a way, though, Calvin is logically consequent. He does not try to affirm God's goodness, so, in one fell swoop, he eliminates all problems (of which the "Canaanite genocides" are the most striking example) that have troubled so many generations of exegetes  and apologists.

Let's take stock:
  • That cosmic evil is the consequence of "original sin" is embarrassingly ridiculous;
  • That cosmic evil is willed by God to afflict humans makes God into a monster.
Is there another option, a way out from this conundrum?

I suggest to examine the very beginning of the Bible, the first two verses of Genesis ...
1 In the beginning God created the heavens and the earth.
2 Now the earth was without shape and empty [תֹ֙הוּ֙ וָבֹ֔הוּ - transl. tohu wa bohu], and darkness was over the surface of the watery deep, but the Spirit of God was moving over the surface of the water.
(Gen 1:1-2
... in particular verse 2, which is, usually, totally disregarded.

Notice how, unlike in Plato's myth of creations, God does not shape pre-existing matter: no, this chaotic matter ("without shape and empty") is the very first act of His creation. In many modern languages (French, German, Estonian, Hungarian), tohu wa bohu (or similar spelling) expresses "utter confusion".

So, when God, in the six days of Creation, gives shape to this primeval matter, a certain amount of chaos remains. Why would God "build on chaos"? The (tentative) answer is in my post Catastrophic Stairway to Freedom:

If Natural Catastrophes (cosmic evil) were banned, Human Freedom would be impossible.

Monday, 4 September 2017

... nobody understands how decisions are made or how imagination is set free

Brain Gears Icon

John Maddox (1925 - 1999, "lecturer in theoretical physics at the University of Manchester from 1949 to 1956 and editor-in-chief of Nature from 1966 to 1973 and from 1980 to 1995"), certainly not a friend of pseudo-science (see his role in debunking homoeopathy claims) and certainly not a friend of woo-woo (see Wikipedia > The Sheldrake editorial 1981, further elaborated in 1994) wrote this, in a paper published posthumously:

The catalogue of our ignorance must also include the understanding of the human brain, which is incomplete in one conspicuous way: nobody understands how decisions are made or how imagination is set free. What consciousness consists of (or how it should be defined) is equally a puzzle. Despite the marvellous successes of neuroscience in the past century (not to mention the disputed relevance of artificial intelligence), we seem as far from understanding cognitive process as we were a century ago.The Unexpected Science to Come, by Sir John Maddox, (Dec 20, 1999, Scientific American, Vol. 281, No. 6, pp. 62-67)

Was it a fair account of the situation in 1999? Has anything significantly changed since?

The problem has very much to do with methodological naturalism (=physicalism), however loosely expressed. 

Scientists should keep using the method of Natural Science to confront questions about the mind and its relation to the body/brain, even if they should suspect that Natural Science may never give fully satisfactory answers, for the simple reason that the method of Natural Science includes essentially (methodological) naturalism. Beyond, there is philosophical speculation, which is perfectly legitimate, BUT which is NOT constrained by (methodological) naturalism. Certainly fancy divagations like "non-reductive physicalism", or "holism" or some other fancy "-ism" are of no help whatsoever.

Dickerson's "Rule No. 1" ....
Rule No. 1: Let us see how far and to what extent we can explain the behaviour of the physical and material universe in terms of purely physical and material causes, without invoking the supernatural.
... in my opinion is the best definition/prescription of methodological naturalism, explicitly refers to the supernatural (which he opposes to "purely physical and material causes"), which means that any hypothesis about the mind, however limited, that cannot be reduced to physical states is simply non-scientific.

Saturday, 2 September 2017

Why wasn't the Logos included in the Nicene Creed?


Emperor Constantine I and the bishops of the Council of Nicaea (325)
holding the Niceno–Constantinopolitan Creed of 381 (sic!)


When the First Ecumenical Council was summoned by Emperor Constantine I at Nicea, in 325 CE, Eusebius of Caesarea came with his local Creed, convinced that it would be accepted, or anyway used as a basis for general Creed of the Catholic Church. Here it is:
“We believe in One God, the Father Almighty, the Maker of all things visible and invisible. And in One Lord Jesus Christ, the Word of God [ho logos tou theou], God from God, Light from Light, Life from Life, Son Only-begotten, first-born of every creature, before all the ages, begotten from the Father, by Whom also all things were made; Who for our salvation was made flesh, and lived among men, and suffered, and rose again the third day, and ascended to the Father, and will come again in glory to judge the quick and dead. And we believe also in One Holy Ghost” (Eusebius of Caesarea, Letter on the Council of Nicaea, @ Catholic Encyclopedia – emphasis added)
In the second article of this Creed, it is declared that the "One Lord Jesus Christ" is the "Word of God" (ho logos tou theou).
If that phrase had been adopted in the Nicene Creed (without any pre-existent personal overtone, but simply stating that ho logos tou theou, in accordance with John 1:14, sarx egeneto – the logos being an essential attribute of the One and Only God), it would have clarified the Catholic doctrine on this essential point. 

Then why wasn’t it included in the Nicene Creed?

Certainly not because the expression isn’t scriptural: in fact it reflects the very contents of the Prologue to the Gospel of John (John 1:1-18). More, unlike homoousios, which is definitely not scriptural, and in fact was even first used by the Gnostics ("before the Gnostics there is no trace at all of its existence" – see von Harnack, Ortiz de Urbina, Mendizabal, Prestige, Gerlitz, Boularand, Kelly, Dinsen, Stead), and was even condemned in at least one of the Synods of Antioch (264 – 269 CE), held against Paul of Samosata.

So why wasn’t it adopted? Perhaps the possible explanation is that what turned out to be the Symbol of the Apostles, in its earliest version (vetus symbolum romanum), was so ancient, that, in fact, it was (probably in its Greek or even Aramaic text) of truly Apostolic origin, so ancient  that it did not incorporate the doctrine expressed in the Prologue to the Gospel of John, which Gospel, for quite some time, was not even included in the Canon.

Here is my hypothesis.

While the Conciliar Fathers at Nicea had no qualm with adopting the un-scriptural, even originally Gnostic homoousios, so as to quash the Arians, they were reluctant to incorporate the fully scriptural logos tou theou, because it was not part of the earliest Apostolic Symbol.

In much later times, Augustine of Hippo showed how much sacred respect there still was for the intangibility of the Symbol of the Apostles. Augustine, who spent many pages on the Symbol of the Apostles (in particular his Sermons from 212 to 218 - although he does not explicitly call it "of the Apostles"), solemnly states, addressing the catechumens:
"You should not write it out in any way, but, so as to hold the exact words of the Creed, learn it by listening. Not even when you have learned it should you write it down, but, rather, always hold it and cherish it in your memory." (Sermon 212 On the Presentation of the Creed, Saint Augustine, Sermons On The Liturgical Seasons, translated by Sister Mary Sarah Muldowney, in The Fathers Of The Church. A New Translation. Volume 38 [<= link to PDF file], p. 120 [144/486])

It is evident from his Sermons that the Symbol to which Augustine makes reference is essentially the same as the vetus symbolum romanum. Unlike Rufinus, who motivates the prohibition to write down the Symbol with the risk that it may end up in hostile hands, Augustine does not motivate his prohibition to put the Symbol in writing. By Augustine’s time, the necessity, dictated by the clandestinity of the early Christian Church, to consider it as a "secret watchword", was superseded. But it is highly significant that the traditional ban was strictly retained.

In recent times, reading a seasoned Journal Article, "The Earliest Text of the Old Roman Symbol: A Debate with Hans Lietzmann and J. N. D. Kelly" (D. Larrimore Holland, Church History, Vol. 34, No. 3, Sep. 1965, pp. 262-281), made me realize the full extent to which those highly respected scholars went so as not to admit the most probable explanation of the close similarity between H and R, viz. that the vetus symbolum romanum was the prototype from which all other regional variants, and all baptismal creeds were derived.

Thursday, 31 August 2017

God’s foreknowledge is incompatible with genuine human freedom

Here are two statements that I consider a truth of crystal clear self-evidence:
Axioms of God’s Foreknowledge vs. Human Freedom 
God’s total foreknowledge is incompatible with genuine human freedom.
God is with us at all times but does NOT know in advance what we'll think or do.
Having stated my “Axioms of God’s Foreknowledge vs. Human Freedom”, I have gradually realized that what is for me self evident, and therefore axiomatic, is not so for many people. This is so, I suspect, in particular for Protestant Christians, in particular of Calvinist ascent. Anyway, I realize that it is necessary to demonstrate what to me is obvious, either directly, or by disproving the opposite, viz. the position that is referred to as "compatibilism", that is:
God’s total foreknowledge is compatible with genuine human freedom.
A typical example can be found in this article by Norman Swartz, Foreknowledge and Free Will @ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

You can read the article, in detail, for yourselves. At some point it gets rather technical, and requires a certain familiarity with Symbolic Logic.
 
I will only concentrate on the essential for my present purpose. The author of the article, Norman Swartz (professor emeritus of philosophy, retired 1998, Simon  Fraser University) gives immediately the clearest possible formulation of the problem, the one that goes back in the 12th century and to the Jewish philosopher Moses Maimonides:
… "Does God know or does He not know that a certain individual will be good or bad? If thou sayest 'He knows', then it necessarily follows that man is compelled to act as God knew beforehand he would act, otherwise God's knowledge would be imperfect. …"
(The Eight Chapters of Maimonides on Ethics [Semonah Perakim]), edited, annotated, and translated with an Introduction by Joseph I. Gorfinkle, pp. 99-100, New York: AMS Press, 1966)
The objection of Norman Swartz to the validity of Moses Maimonides’ statement has been summed up by saying that what Norman Swartz affirms it is vitiated by a logical fallacy, the modal fallacy.
 
Logical Symbolism
   
To examine the objection that Norman Swartz raises against Moses Maimonides, one has to become familiar with some logical symbolism used in his paper:
   
P, Q, R, ... are  propositions, that is objective statements (see note #3 in Swartz’ paper)
   
  ~P: it is not the case that P (Example: It is not the case that copper conducts electricity. Note: "P" and "~P" have opposite truth-values – whichever is true, the other is false.)
   
  P > Q: if P, then Q (Implication. Example: If she is late, (then) the meeting will be delayed.)
   
  gKP: God knows that P (Example: God knows that the Mississippi River flows north to south.)
   
  ◊P: it is (logically) possible that P (Example: It is (logically) possible that the United States was defeated in World War II. (Note: Whatever is not self-contradictory is logically possible.)
 
  ☐P: It is (logically) necessary that P (Example: It is logically necessary that every number has a double. (Note: If Q is not logically possible, then ~Q is logically necessary.)
 
  ∇P: It is contingent that P (Example: It is contingent that the United States purchased Alaska from Russia. (Note: A proposition, Q, is contingent if and only if Q and ~Q.)
 
  : it necessarily follows (It is the conclusion, viz. the proposition that follows logically and necessarily follows one or more propositions that are called premises. The conclusion is at the bottom, separated from the premises by a horizontal line   ____ )
_______
  
Swartz’ exam of Maimonides’ argument and (presumed) modal fallacy
 
Herebelow I have copied entirely form his paper, Swartz’ exam of Maimonides’ argument and (presumed) modal fallacy  (see 6b. The Modal Fallacy in Epistemic Determinism

Let's recall Maimonides's argument:
… "Does God know or does He not know that a certain individual will be good or bad? If thou sayest 'He knows', then it necessarily follows that [that] man is compelled to act as God knew beforehand he would act, otherwise God's knowledge would be imperfect."
We can symbolize the core of this argument, using "" for "it necessarily follows"; and "" for "compelled" [necessitated]; and "D" for the proposition describing what some particular person does tomorrow.
 
  gKD  [“God knows what a particular person will do tomorrow”]
  ____ [“implies that”]
 
D [“it necessarily follows what that particular person will do tomorrow]
 
  There seems to be (at least) one missing premise. [In the terminology of logicians, the argument is enthymematic.] One tacit assumption of this argument is the necessary truth, "it is not possible both for God to know that D and for D to be false", or, in symbols, " ~ (gKD & ~D)". So the argument becomes:
 
  gKD  [“God knows what a particular person will do tomorrow”]
  ~ (gKD & ~D) ["it is not possible both for God to know that D and for D to be false"]
  ____ [“imply that”]
 
D [“it necessarily follows what that particular person will do tomorrow]
 
  But even with this repair, the argument remains invalid. The conclusion does not follow from the two premises. To derive the conclusion, a third premise is needed, and it is easy to see what it is. Most persons, with hardly a moment's thought, virtually as a reflex action, will tacitly assume that the second premise is logically equivalent to:
 
  gKD
D [“If God knows what a particular person will do tomorrow, then what that person will do tomorrow is (not contingent but) necessary”]
 
  and will tacitly (/unconsciously) add this further premise, so as to yield, finally:
 
  gKD  [“God knows what a particular person will do tomorrow”]
  ~ (gKD & ~D) ["it is not possible both for God to know that D and for D to be false"]
  
gKD D [“If God knows what a particular person will do tomorrow, then what that person will do tomorrow is (not contingent but) necessary”]
  ____ [“imply that”]
 
D [“it necessarily follows what that particular person will be compelled to do tomorrow]
 
  [Swartz’ conclusion]
 
  But this third premise, we have seen above, is false; it commits the modal fallacy. Without this premise, Maimonides' argument is invalid; with it, the argument becomes valid but unsound (i.e. has a false and essential premise [viz. the third one]). Either way, the argument is a logical botch.

  Once the logical error is detected, and removed, the argument for epistemic determinism simply collapses. If some future action/choice is known prior to its occurrence, that event does not thereby become "necessary", "compelled", "forced", or what have you. Inasmuch as its description was, is, and will remain forever contingent, both it and its negation remain possible. Of course only one of the two was, is, and will remain true; while the other was, is, and will remain false. But truth and falsity, per se, do not determine a proposition's modality. Whether true or false, each of these propositions was, is, and will remain possible. Knowing – whether by God or a human being – some future event no more forces that event to occur than our learning that dinosaurs lived in (what is now) South Dakota forced those reptiles to take up residence there.
  Criticism of Swartz’ criticism of Maimonides’ (presumed) modal fallacy
 
  I have no objection concerning Swartz’ analysis of Maimonides’ argument, and on the "implicit premises" that Swartz extracts from Maimonides’ argument.

It is
Swartz’ conclusion that, far from exposing Maimonides’ argument (complete with the three explicit premises) as “unsound” and as a “logical botch” emphasizes Swartz’ own fallacy, in the case of God.
 
  Swartz affirms that the “third premise” (symbolically 
gKD D, viz. “If God knows what a particular person will do tomorrow, then what that person will do tomorrow is (not contingent but) necessary”, is false and essential, because … “Inasmuch as its description was, is, and will remain forever contingent, both it and its negation remain possible.”
 
  Now, while all the above is, from a strictly logical POV, impeccable, I affirm that it cannot apply to God, if God is considered totally omniscient  and omnipotent, and that, in fact,  contrary to what Swartz says, in the case that
God is considered totally omniscient  and omnipotent, the “third premise” is essential AND true, because, if it wasn’t, then God would be either NOT omniscient, OR NOT omnipotent, OR both.
 
  An example will be sufficient to show that Mt. Swartz'  mountain is nothing but a molehill. 
 
D: God foreknows that the the Sheriff Pat Garret will shoot and kill the bandit Billy the Kid, at age 21, in Fort Sumner on July 14, 1881
  
If Billy the Kid escapes death, then God is NOT Omniscient. Or he is NOT Omnipotent, because he did not "steer" events so as to make them correspond to His foreknowledge. 
 
Q.E.D.

Tuesday, 29 August 2017

Basil in search of the hypostasis

No, its not Basil with the Arab Phoenix, but Ahmed with a Bald Ibis ...

Basil of Caesarea (ca. 329 - 379) was the Greek bishop of Caesarea Mazaca in Cappadocia. His brother was Gregory of Nyssa. With Gregory of Nazianzus, the three are collectively referred to as the Cappadocian Fathers.  

Some time ago, in his blog Eclectic Orthodoxy,  Fr Aidan (Alvin) Kimel wrote a post by the title St Basil the Great and the Search for Hypostasis (14 July 2013). 

Here are my notes of comment and criticism. (I suggest that, first you read Fr Aidan's post.) 

Fr Aidan Kimel obviously is an apologist, more, an enthusiast of the Cappadocians. I think they are possibly the worse thing that could happen to Christianity at the most critical time, so much so that I prefer to call them the Cappadocian scoundrels, for the mischievousness of their deeds, viz. concocting the doctrine of the (co-equal, co-eternal, tri-personal) Trinity, which, with good peace of deluded advocates, was and is nothing but a political ploy, designed to reconcile, after some 60 years of strife, the (neo) Nicenes with the (semi) Arians. Sadly for Christianity, they succeeded.

In his post, Fr Aidan says that in 377 CE Amphilochius of Iconium wrote to St Basil and asked him to explain the distinction between ousia and hypostasis. Basil responded with a statement that Fr Aidan reproduces in his post, from Basil's Letter 236 §6. 

N.B. Fr Aidan Kimel's quotation does not include the end of §6, perhaps because it was not included in his source (John Behr, Nicene Faith, II, p. 298), perhaps because the omitted part would have been rather embarrassing. Here is the quotation of the omitted part of §6:
On the other hand those who identify essence or substance [ousia] and hypostasis are compelled to confess only three Persons [prosopa], and, in their hesitation to speak of three hypostases, are convicted of failure to avoid the error of Sabellius, for even Sabellius himself, who in many places confuses the conception, yet, by asserting that the same hypostasis changed its form to meet the needs of the moment, does endeavour to distinguish persons [prosopa].  (“Basil the Great on Ousia and Hypostasis”, Letters, 236. 6  @ earlychurchtexts.com; St. Basil of Caesarea, Letter 236 @ newadvent.org)
The above quotation shows how difficult it was, even for Basil of Caesarea, to replace prosopon with his his new-found pet word, hypostasis.

Anyway, Basil may try as much as he likes to explain the difference between hypostasis and ousia to a perplexed Amphilochius of Iconium. The fact remains that those definitions are entirely his invention, without the faintest basis in Aristotle and in previous usage. So much so that John Behr “suggests that Basil is working with the distinction proposed by Aristotle between primary and secondary substance”. By this, John Behr adds to the confusion, because, the “particular or individual substance” (say, Paul, or Timothy, or Silvanus) is precisely what Aristotle refers to as “primary ousia” whereas the “given essence” is precisely what Aristotle refers to as “secondary ousia” (for instance, man).

Athanasius was perfectly aware of this abusive use of hypostasis by the Cappadocians, so much so that he continued to refer to God as "one substance" mia hypostasis.

Around the Synod of Alexandria of 362 (see Socrates Scholasticus > Church History, Book III, ch. 7-8), the Latins tried to translate the Cappadocian formula ena ousia en treis hypostaseis with una essentia in tribus substantiis, and they were horrified, because they perceived it as tri-theistic, through and through.

So as to stop being scandalized, the Latins had to invent a new word to replace substantia, as a translation for hypostasis: subsistentia. But, as the Online Etymological Dictionary appropriately says,
“Latin subsistentia is a loan-translation of Greek hypostasis, "foundation, substance, real nature, subject matter; that which settles at the bottom, sediment," literally "anything set under."” [entry subsistence]
In the concluding remark of his post St Basil the Great and the Search for Hypostasis, however, Fr Kimel is honest enough to admit: 
“I must note that my language in the last two paragraphs reflects later Church usage. For Basil, as for Jesus and the Apostles, the one God is the Father.”
Unfortunately, this is precisely the problem with Eastern Orthodox Christianity: whether they are aware of it or not,  they have never let go of (a certain amount of) Subordinationism.

Still not convinced that the Eastern Orthodox understanding of the Trinity is ultimately Modalistic Monarchianism?  Then read what Fr Kimelwrites, just before the previous admission:
"The only difference between the Three is how each is the one God—not a difference in substance but of mode of existence." (St Basil the Great and the Search for Hypostasis, cit. - emphasis added)